Skip navigation
Please use this identifier to cite or link to this item: http://arks.princeton.edu/ark:/88435/dsp01qf85nb42f
Full metadata record
DC FieldValueLanguage
dc.contributor.advisorMorison, Benjamin C.en_US
dc.contributor.authorBaker, Samuel Hunteren_US
dc.contributor.otherPhilosophy Departmenten_US
dc.date.accessioned2014-01-15T15:05:07Z-
dc.date.available2016-01-15T06:09:30Z-
dc.date.issued2014en_US
dc.identifier.urihttp://arks.princeton.edu/ark:/88435/dsp01qf85nb42f-
dc.description.abstractAristotle begins the Nicomachean Ethics by emphasizing that the virtuous person should understand the nature of the best good achievable by humans in action, something Aristotle calls the "human good." In Nicomachean Ethics I 7, he defines the human good as "activity of the <rational part of the human> soul on the basis of virtue and if there are more virtues than one, on the basis of the best and most end-like and moreover in an end-like [i.e. complete] life." The argument by which he arrives at this definition is known as the ergon argument. This dissertation aims to improve our understanding of the definition by analyzing how it follows from this argument. My interpretation is novel, as I reject the ubiquitous assumption that the ergon of an X is always the proper activity of that X. I argue instead that the ergon of an X is an activity in some cases but a product in others, depending on what the X is. Thus, while the ergon of the flautist is his performance (an activity), the ergon of the sculptor is a sculpture (a product). This enables us to see that the fundamental rationale of the ergon is that just as the best achievement of a sculptor is a certain version of his ergon, which is a sculpture, so the best achievement of a human will be a certain version of his ergon, which is an activity of the rational part of the human soul. When Aristotle adds the further features "on the basis of virtue," "on the basis of the best virtue," and "in a complete life" he does so in order to mark off the best achievement of a human from the mere proper achievement of a human. Observing this enables us to see how a monistic reading of the definition--on which the "best virtue" is theoretical wisdom--could in fact follow from the premises of the ergon argument. It also enables us to understand the proper explanation for why "in a complete life" is added, namely, because continuity and perpetuity make the best activity even better.en_US
dc.language.isoenen_US
dc.publisherPrinceton, NJ : Princeton Universityen_US
dc.relation.isformatofThe Mudd Manuscript Library retains one bound copy of each dissertation. Search for these copies in the <a href=http://catalog.princeton.edu> library's main catalog </a>en_US
dc.subjectAristotleen_US
dc.subjectErgonen_US
dc.subjectEudaimoniaen_US
dc.subjectFunctionen_US
dc.subjectHappinessen_US
dc.subject.classificationPhilosophyen_US
dc.subject.classificationClassical studiesen_US
dc.titleDefining the Human Good: Aristotle's Ergon Argumenten_US
dc.typeAcademic dissertations (Ph.D.)en_US
pu.projectgrantnumber690-2143en_US
pu.embargo.terms2016-01-15en_US
Appears in Collections:Philosophy

Files in This Item:
File Description SizeFormat 
Baker_princeton_0181D_10849.pdf1.85 MBAdobe PDFView/Download


Items in Dataspace are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise indicated.