Skip navigation
Please use this identifier to cite or link to this item: http://arks.princeton.edu/ark:/88435/dsp012z10wq261
Full metadata record
DC FieldValueLanguage
dc.contributor.advisorRosen, Gideon Aen_US
dc.contributor.authorBudolfson, Mark Bryanten_US
dc.contributor.otherPhilosophy Departmenten_US
dc.date.accessioned2012-11-15T23:57:23Z-
dc.date.available2014-11-15T06:00:30Z-
dc.date.issued2012en_US
dc.identifier.urihttp://arks.princeton.edu/ark:/88435/dsp012z10wq261-
dc.description.abstractSome collective action problems are easy. For example, if a tragedy of the commons arises within a nation's borders, and if it is clear that the problem can be solved only by a particular kind of coercive governmental response, and if it is clear that every citizen would want the government to adopt such a response, then the government should adopt such a response, and such a response is justified. This is an easy collective action problem because it is obvious what course of action should be taken, and it is also clear enough why that course of action would be justified. In this dissertation I answer questions that arise from the most difficult collective action problems, such as our situation with respect to climate change, with respect to which neither economists nor philosophers have made any real progress. For example, in the first chapter I answer the following question: What should we do when we face a collective action problem that is impervious to our standard tools for achieving cooperation and avoiding a tragic outcome? In other words, what should we do when we are unable to rely on benevolent human dispositions, natural `market-based' coordination, bargaining, governmental coercion, and other familiar mechanisms to avoid an undesirable outcome? My answer is that even when our standard tools are useless, we can often escape a tragic dilemma by turning the force of such a dilemma against itself. The trick is to intentionally place ourselves into a new dilemma of our own design, the predictable outcome of which is a desirable solution to the initial, otherwise insoluble dilemma. For example, with respect to anthropogenic climate change, where any effective response will be contrary to the interests of the current citizens of many nations, the trick is to engineer and introduce an international climate treaty that creates something like a multi-player prisoner's dilemma at the level of nations, the predictable outcome of which is that all nations will agree to the treaty, thereby making the current citizens of some of those nations worse off relative to the no-treaty status quo as a side-effect of a mechanism within the treaty that effectively combats climate change. I show that such a treaty is the only attractive option if - as seems true - we must secure the cooperation of many influential nations whose current citizens will be made worse off by any effective response, and if such nations are disposed to reject or pull out of treaties whenever they are contrary to the interests of their current citizens. I also explain why such a treaty is the key to engineering the most ethical climate treaty possible, and to making genuine progress beyond the unpromising incrementalist, idealist, and hard-headed realist approaches to climate treaties that dominate the literature in philosophy, politics, economics, and law. More generally, the result is a straightforward, realistic, and non-coercive framework for constructing economically and ethically optimal solutions to many previously intractable collective action problems. In a later chapter I show that nations can be justified in acting in ways that make their citizens worse off, are unfair to their citizens, and that would be reasonably rejected by their citizens - which provides a counterexample to many political theories. Such situations arise most clearly when the citizens of a nation are, through no fault of their own, morally required to favor a national course of action that is unfair to them, contrary to their interests, and contrary to the interests of future generations of their descendants and fellow citizens. Arguably, the United States is in such a situation with respect to climate change, given that inaction on the part of the US may well ensure a catastrophic outcome for untold billions of future people, and given that any real solution to the problem arguably requires the US to agree to a climate treaty that is unfair to its citizens and contrary to their interests. At the same time, even given the gravest worst-case-scenario assumptions about the effects of climate change, I argue that individual citizens are not required to reduce their emissions by a significant amount, because without an effective global response such reductions are both costly and futile in a way that makes such reductions not required. In fact, I argue that such futility and lack of requirement at the individual level explains why individuals are required to favor a coercive intergovernmental response to climate change, and why nations are justified in adopting such a response even if it is unfair to their citizens and contrary to their interests. (Here it might be useful to recall that in the first chapter I explain why an effective intergovernmental solution is realistic even given pessimistic assumptions about the collective action problem that arises at the level of nations.) In the course of arguing for these conclusions, I make progress on a number of issues at the foundations of normative ethics and political philosophy. Among other things, I identify the subtle contours of the ethical significance of futility, which has not been adequately investigated by philosophers and other theorists, and is of great practical and theoretical importance, because worries about the futility of individual action arise in almost every area of practical concern, and threaten to undermine most normative theories. In the course of my discussion, I show that existent normative theories are unable to offer a plausible account of what individuals are required to do in the kind of collective action situations that are commonplace in a market-based society, and are therefore unable to explain many of the most important facts about modern moral life. In particular, results from economics and political science that have been unappreciated by philosophers help to clarify that for straightforward mathematical and empirical reasons an appeal to expected consequences cannot possibly deliver the verdicts on such cases that consequentialists themselves assume. In addition, alternative theories that appeal to `universalizability', `direct harm', and other notions also cannot deliver plausible verdicts on such cases. For these and other reasons, I argue that a plausible account of what individuals are required to do in a large market-based society must invoke a distinction between activities that are essential to a product or to the actual production of a product, and activities that are not. These and other results related to futility have important practical implications, because many serious practical issues are tied to situations in which the action of individuals is in some sense futile - for example, whether individuals are required to contribute to charities that help innocent people who are suffering from easily curable afflictions, whether it is permissible to consume animal products given the terrible way that many animals are treated, whether it is permissible to consume products that are produced in a way that harms or exploits other people, and, of course, whether individuals are required to reduce their greenhouse gas emissions. In the last two chapters I show that morality and other forms of normativity are sometimes dramatically directly collectively self-defeating, where a normative system has that property when it requires everyone to act in a way that everyone can see is certain to be dramatically worse along the relevant normative dimension than if everyone did not follow the requirements of that normative system instead. This shows that a wide range of normative theories are either false, or at least don't have the consequences that their adherents take them to have, including consequentialist theories, contractualist theories, Kantian theories, universalization theories, enlightened self-interest theories, and many other normative theories. It also means that morality and other forms of normativity cannot be relied upon to solve collective action problems even in a world of normatively flawless agents. One practical upshot is that even when a disaster will ensue if everyone acts in a particular way or on a particular principle, that doesn't settle the question of whether individuals are permitted to act in that way or on that principle. In sum, I provide answers to the most pressing questions about what we should do about difficult collective action problems, especially when non-cooperation would lead to catastrophe.en_US
dc.language.isoenen_US
dc.publisherPrinceton, NJ : Princeton Universityen_US
dc.relation.isformatofThe Mudd Manuscript Library retains one bound copy of each dissertation. Search for these copies in the <a href=http://catalog.princeton.edu> library's main catalog </a>en_US
dc.subjectClimate Changeen_US
dc.subjectCollective Actionen_US
dc.subjectDerek Parfiten_US
dc.subjectEthicsen_US
dc.subjectJusticeen_US
dc.subjectPeter Singeren_US
dc.subject.classificationPhilosophyen_US
dc.subject.classificationEconomicsen_US
dc.subject.classificationPolitical Scienceen_US
dc.titleCollective Action, Climate Change, and the Ethical Significance of Futilityen_US
dc.typeAcademic dissertations (Ph.D.)en_US
pu.projectgrantnumber690-2143en_US
pu.embargo.terms2014-11-15en_US
Appears in Collections:Philosophy

Files in This Item:
File Description SizeFormat 
Budolfson_princeton_0181D_10143.pdf1.37 MBAdobe PDFView/Download


Items in Dataspace are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise indicated.