Skip navigation
Please use this identifier to cite or link to this item: http://arks.princeton.edu/ark:/88435/dsp01pc289j147
Full metadata record
DC FieldValueLanguage
dc.contributor.advisorGeorge, Robert P.en_US
dc.contributor.advisorBatnitzky, Leora F.en_US
dc.contributor.authorMark, Daniel Ianen_US
dc.contributor.otherPolitics Departmenten_US
dc.date.accessioned2013-05-21T13:33:45Z-
dc.date.available2015-05-21T05:14:57Z-
dc.date.issued2013en_US
dc.identifier.urihttp://arks.princeton.edu/ark:/88435/dsp01pc289j147-
dc.description.abstractThis dissertation addresses the nature of legal obligation and the so-called dilemma of authority, which asks how authority can be both content-independent, meaning authoritative without respect to the substance of the directives, and legitimate, a normative judgment that necessarily depends on the content. Contemporary accounts of law's authority, often because they build on the work of HLA Hart and Joseph Raz, are largely inadequate. Hart, on one hand, identifies obligation as the central feature of law, which distinguishes it from criminal coercion, but, on the other hand, characterizes law as rules based in social practice, which do not necessarily entail an obligation to obey. Raz, while also a positivist, tries to account for law's normative authority, locating it in the conformity of laws with the reasons subjects already have for action. This form of legitimacy, however, explains only when obedience to the law is permissible, not when it is obligatory. Indeed, Raz concludes that there is no obligation to obey the law just because it is the law. Furthermore, with a theory of law as expertise, Raz cannot say why the law, among all other schemes, is authoritative. Instead, a legal system should be seen as a set of commands oriented on the whole to the common good. Conceptually, legal obligation is composed of both commands and reasons, drawing on models of religious obligation and moral obligation, respectively. The descriptive aspect, command, captures law's intention to obligate and refers to the commander (in whatever institutional form), who is the one designated to bear the authority. The normative aspect, the common good, supplies the justification for law's authority through people's obligations to the common good. In this way, the law has general authority and can obligate even when it is not good in all its particulars. The views of Yves Simon and John Finnis strongly support this connection between law, authority, and the common good. In addition, the work of Carl Schmitt on sovereignty and political theology, which emphasizes the importance of authoritativeness yet rejects positivism, offers a complementary parallel to the concept of law in this dissertation.en_US
dc.language.isoenen_US
dc.publisherPrinceton, NJ : Princeton Universityen_US
dc.relation.isformatofThe Mudd Manuscript Library retains one bound copy of each dissertation. Search for these copies in the <a href=http://catalog.princeton.edu> library's main catalog </a>en_US
dc.subjectauthorityen_US
dc.subjectlawen_US
dc.subjectlegalen_US
dc.subjectlegalityen_US
dc.subjectlegitimacyen_US
dc.subjectobligationen_US
dc.subject.classificationPolitical Scienceen_US
dc.subject.classificationLawen_US
dc.titleAuthority and Legal Obligationen_US
dc.typeAcademic dissertations (Ph.D.)en_US
pu.projectgrantnumber690-2143en_US
pu.embargo.terms2015-05-21en_US
Appears in Collections:Politics

Files in This Item:
File Description SizeFormat 
Mark_princeton_0181D_10575.pdf1.1 MBAdobe PDFView/Download


Items in Dataspace are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise indicated.